Balancing
by Al Katz
Al Katz is a Professor
of Law, State University of New York at Buffalo, Faculty of
Law and Jurisprudence. This paper originally appeared as a Buffalo
Critical Legal Studies Monograph, 1983. This article is the
product of the Balancing Seminar at Buffalo, 1978-1982, whose
members included: Kathleen McDermott, Elizabeth Mensch, Richard
Milan, Dennis Patterson, Melanie Pierson, Rochelle Reback, Judith
Romanowski, Lee Smith, John Troll, William Bozzuffi, Betsy Broder,
David Bryan, William Clauss, Peter Diamond, Herbert Eisenberg,
Alan Freeman, Philip Halpern, Jacob Hyman, Joseph Kelemen, Gene
Krauss, Virginia Leary, Stephen Wieczorek, Gary Wojtan, John
Ziegler.
"The coalescence
of a research paradigm creates the possibility of an accumulation
of knowledge, and thus the phenomenon of scholarly progress.
What is less often recognized, for the human sciences at least,
is that any consolidation of a paradigm depends on the exclusion,
or relegation to the status of 'art', of those elements of the
changing discipline which call the credentials of the discipline
itself into question, those research practices which . . . work
at the edges of disorder." James Clifford, On Ethnographic
Surrealism, 23 Comparative Study of Society and History 539,
554 (1981).
The Seminar gratefully
acknowledges the contribution of visitors: Paul Diesing, Fred
Konefsky, Howard Berman, Elizabeth Mensch, Duncan Kennedy.
I.
Why the 'Background of Truth' 18
II. Binary Choices and Middle
Positions 21
III. Litigation and the Objectivity
of Represented Interests 24
IV. The Opening of Science and
Social Interests 26
V. Civil Society and Normativity;
Political Society and Representation 27
VI. The Productions of Representation,
Expertise and Balancing 31
Notes |
III.
It is impossible to imagine a viable society truly respecting
the great Hegelian division between a civil society marked by
an absolute subjectivity of interests and a political society
in which the state encloses as its essence an irreducible general
interest. At least since the end of the 18th century two great
mediating strategies were dispersed throughout liberal society
to carry the twin burden of preventing collapse into a chaos
of subjectivity and undermining the tyrannical tendency of a
unified and general interest. First, the elaboration of relatively
objective interests and their distribution into weakly bounded
and overlapping categories that would nevertheless function
to organize diversity. Second, the penetration of representational
relations to the deepest levels of social life in order to resemble
and reassemble diversity throughout the structures of family,
neighborhood, city, workplace, bureaucracy, political party,
protest group, region and so forth. Subjective interests must
find their expression in the objective forms of father, worker,
woman, farmer, southerner, unemployed, disabled, or investor
in order to be represented — to be made a living presence
capable of speaking in some other place at some special time
when the interest might be heard and respected or ignored and
denied. Representation — that mercurial notion breathing
life into liberal political society — owes nothing to
the extensions and contractions of suffrage but owes everything
to the double functioning of objectified interests. Fundamentally,
interests in the objective sense are midpoints between diversity
and unity: they reduce subjectivity to a finite listing, an
assignment of traits, strengths, biases and passions. Representation
is grounded in this transformation of an absolutely subjective
civil society into a series of determined and specified relations.
This function of objectified interests might be called, with
some plausibility, communicating from civil society to political
society. But there is also a reverse flow, a movement that shapes
and conditions, that articulates upon diverse interests a specific
organization and a certain manner of speaking if it expects
to be heard. Because it is an exclusive voice, because it holds
a monopoly of political power, representation exerts an immediate
pressure on civil society that forces it to extrude only legitimate
interests. What come to be understood as interests, recognized
interests, or legitimate interests are the consequence of this
double movement according to which objectified interests may
be represented and representation requires objective interests.
This excursion into the interpenetration and mutual dependence
of representation and interest proved fruitful. There could
be no question that balancing practice depended heavily upon
the identification of interests by someone in some relevant
context. Representing client interests was surely one such context,
but there was also the investigation of legislative history
to lay bare statutory meaning by inference from an intention
or purpose to protect or suppress certain interests. The specification
of interests was invariably required by arguments addressed
to the vindication of constitutional rights; explications, attacks
and defenses of controversial matters such as the exclusionary
rule, the habeas corpus jurisdiction rule or the void-for-vagueness
doctrine were organized around a frequently creative detailing
of the interests served and/or undermined by expansion or contraction
of application. And virtually all modem contract law teachers,
having supped at the table of legal realism, point out to their
students that the interest of contracting parties is in performance
not a lawsuit. Even garden variety legal literature places interest
identification and analysis at the center of balancing practice,
as in Gunther's 1973 article praising the skill of Justice Powell
as a balancer. Representation seemed critical because of the
suspicion that interests were being invented by lawyers and
judges to suit the occasion.
Precisely because the truth of specified interests could not
be found in the purity of an empiricist fantasy, precisely because
a relevant interest could not be identified by interrogating
the desire of an individual subject or even an implicated group,
the question of an originating source responsible for speaking
in the name of objectified interests could not be avoided. Even
if it were the client who originally represented an interest
to the lawyer, plainly the organization, formulation and presentation
of a legitimate interest depended upon the lawyer to represent
it as a reality. Nothing required judicial acceptance of such
representations, of course, so additional or modified versions
of presented interests could easily become central to the balancing
operation. Suppose a worker who lost his pension because the
company terminated his plan a few months before benefits would
have vested in him complains of insufficient disclosure under
assertedly applicable regulations of the Securities Exchange
Commission, a complaint that requires characterizing the pension
as an investment security. Nothing prevents a judge from 'finding'
that employees work for wages and are not investors with a security
interest. This judgment may certainly be read as an observation
about workers' attitude toward labor and its alleged rewards
that necessarily rejects the security interest argument as a
piece of creative lawyering calculated to give the client a
shot at winning an otherwise hopeless lawsuit.
|
Studying the movement
of interests in balancing practice was gloomy and depressing
business when following the path neither deepened nor enlightened
but merely lead back into hoary issues of positive jurisprudence
— the law-fact distinction counted among such debris.
Where, for example, a defendant claims that the evidence against
him was unconstitutionally seized from premises owned, occupied
or otherwise controlled by another person, the judge may reply
that he has no legitimate interest in securing or protecting
the privacy of another. This may be read as a statement about
the empirical existence of a legitimate, objectified interest
(noting, of course, that the expectations or desires of this
particular defendant are immaterial); it may be read as a determination
of substantive Fourth Amendment law; it may specify a procedural
mechanics reflecting institutional considerations and have no
bearing on social interests or the law of search and seizure.
Such instances suggest that expecting interest recognition and
analysis to provide legality with an incremental rationality
is rather foolish.
Depressing though it might be, following the movement of interest
analysis back into the law-fact dichotomy locates it within
a traditional discourse and thus clothes it with a dubious legitimacy
— dubious, that is, relative to alternative explications
with a more radical tendency to undermine confidence in the
rule of law. Objectified interests may be little more than subjective
values packaged to permit their attribution to actual people
under specified circumstances, or universalized and attributed
to the state. Thus an interest in health and life may be attributed
to the state when it opposes an abortion rights claim but not
when it would support the receipt of payments by welfare claimants
or secure decent treatment to prisoners. A judge's values may
require maintaining the distinction between labor and capital
by rejecting any suggestion that capital is little more than
stored labor. This value preference will appear in his opinion
as an interest in income from wages attributed to workers generally
and not as the subjective desire of this worker or group of
workers. On the other hand, any suggestion that a judge who
is himself an active investor should be disqualified for conflict
of interest would be rejected unless he was interested in this
particular corporate litigant.
The structure of adversity augments the suspicion that interest
analysis is a disingenuous vehicle for the introduction of values.
Naive students may suppose that the injunction to take account
of all relevant interests requires specification of those supporting
the opposing claim as well as those cutting against it. In the
previously mentioned search and seizure case, for example, a
compelling interest in the protection of civil liberties might
plausibly be attributed to the state since the latter is primarily
responsible for supervising the behavior of its agents. Combining
this interest with that of the defendant claiming the evidence
illegally seized is being used against him might well produce
a balanced decision in his favor. But the premise of adversity
appears to entail a truncated range of interest identification
unless the interests can be normally distributed among adverse
parties. The legal literature surrounding the exclusionary rule
is largely chaotic due to its inability to specify or justify
the distribution of interests among possible representatives.
If the defendant has a weak interest in deterring illegal enforcement
activity, particularly in habeas corpus, the state may have
a powerful if not compelling one. But the general assumption
seems to be that the interest in deterrence rises and falls
with defendant's stature as a representative of it; the possibility
of selecting another representative for this interest is not
considered a viable option within the context.
Following the movement of interest identification and analysis
with these few examples yields a number of fairly basic propositions:
interest analysis may simply reintroduce an unenlightened revision
of the law-fact problematic into contemporary legal discourse;
it may also provide an excellent vehicle for the injection of
otherwise illegitimate subjective value preferences disguised
as attributed objectified interests; the impact or relevance
of an interest may be a function of the representative selected
to articulate and defend it; judgments respecting the representation
of interests are not merely passive reflectors of an already
determined social truth but contribute to the development and
shaping of concrete social relations. Putting this last point
in other terms, given the legal statements described above,
what must workers do to have savings understood as investments
in their future security; what must citizens do to create an
interest in precluding the illegal invasion of premises not
personally owned or occupied? To the precise extent nothing
can be done within concrete social relations to create, modify
or destroy interests, they must be understood as merely the
phantasms of a warped and dissembling professional 'methodology'.
|